loading

Logout succeed

Logout succeed. See you again!

ebook img

The dual fibration in elementary terms PDF

file size0.06 MB
languageEnglish

Preview The dual fibration in elementary terms

The dual fibration in elementary terms 5 1 0 Anders Kock 2 n a J We give an elementary construction of the dual fibration of a fibration. It 8 does not use the non-elementary notion of (pseudo-) functor into the category of ] categories. In fact, it is clear that the construction we present makes sense for T C internalcategoriesand fibrationsin anyexact category. . ThedualfibrationofafibrationX →BoverBisdescribedine.g.[Borceux] h t II.8.3 via a pseudofunctor F : Bop →Cat (the category of categories), by com- a m posingF withthe(covarariant!) dualizationfunctorCat →Cat;choosingsuchan [ F is tantamount to choosing a cleavage for the fibration. In the present section, we give an alternative description of the dual fibration, which is elementary and 1 v choice-free. 7 4 9 1 Fibrations 1 0 . 1 Werecall here someclassicalnotions. 0 Letp :X →B beanyfunctor. Fora :A→BinB,andforobjectsX,Y ∈X 5 1 withp (X)=Aandp (Y)=B,lethoma (X,Y)bethesetofarrowsh:X →Y inX v: with p (h)=a . For any arrow x :C→A, and any object Z ∈X with p (Z)=C, i X post-compositionwithhdefines a map r a h∗ :homx (Z,X)→homx .a (Z,Y). (we compose from left to right). Recall that h is called Cartesian if this map is a bijection,forall suchx and Z. If h is Cartesian, the injectivity of h implies the cancellation property that h ∗ is “monic w.r. to p ”, meaning that for parallel arrows k,k′ in X with codomain X,and withp (k)=p (k′), wehavethat k.h=k′.h impliesk=k′. Forlateruse,we recall abasicfact: Lemma 1.1 If k=k′.h isCartesian,andh isCartesianthen k′ is Cartesian. 1 The functor p :X →B is called a fibrationif for every a :A→B in B and anyY ∈X withp (Y)=B,thereexistsaCartesianarrowovera withcodomainY. ThefibreoverA∈B isthecategorywhoseobjectsaretheX ∈X withp (X)=A, andwhosearrowsarearrowsinX whichbyp mapto1 ;sucharrowsarecalled A vertical(overA). All this is standard, dating back essentially to early French category theory (Grothendieck, Chevalley, Giraud, Bénabou,...). For a modern account, see [1] II.8.1, [2] B.1.3, or [3]. Note that these notions are elementary (they make sense for category objects in any left exact category), and they do not depend on the non-elementarynotionsofcleavage, orCat-valuedpseudofunctor. 2 The “factorization system” for a fibration Inthediagramsbelow,wetrytomakedisplayverticalarrowsvertically,andCarte- sianarrows horizontally. Recall from the literature that if p : X → B is a fibration, then every arrow z in X may be written as a compositeof a vertical arrow followedby a cartesian arrow. And, crucially, thisdecompositionof z is uniquemoduloa uniquevertical isomorphism. Or,equivalently,moduloanarrowwhichisatthesametimevertical and cartesian. (Recall that for vertical arrows, cartesian is equivalent to isomor- phism (= invertible).) This means that every arrow z in X may be represented by a pair (v,h) of arrows with v vertical and h cartesian, with z = v.h. Thus the codomainofvis thedomainofh. Wecall such apair a“vh compositionpair”, to maketheanalogywithvhspans,tobeconsideredbelow,moreexplicit. Twosuch pairs(v,h)and(v′,h′)representthesamearrowiffthereexistsaverticalcartesian (necessarily unique,and necessarily invertible)i suchthat v.i=v′ andi.h′ =h. (1) We say that (v,h) and (v′,h′) are equivalent if this holds. The composition of arrows in X can be described in terms of representative vh composition pairs, as follows. If z is represented by (v ,h ) for j = 1,2, then z .z is represented j j j 1 2 by (v .w,k.h ), where k is cartesian over p (h ) and w is vertical, and the square 1 2 1 2 displayedcommutes: · v 1 ❄ h · 1 ✲ · w v 2 ❄ ❄ · ✲ · ✲ · k h 2 Such k and w exists (uniquely, up to unique vertical cartesian arrows): construct first k as a cartesian lift of p (h ), then use the universal property of cartesian 1 arrowsto constructw. Thearrows z and z may be inserted, completingthe diagramwith two com- 1 2 mutative triangles, since z = v .h . But if we refrain from doing so, we have a j j j blueprint for a succinct and choice-free description of the fibrewise dual X ∗ of thefibration X →B. Note that a vh factorization of an arrow in X is much reminiscent of the factorizationforanE-M factorizationsystem,asin[Borceux]I.5.5,say,(withthe class of vertical arrows playing the role of E, and the class of cartesian arrows playingtheroleofM;however,notethatnoteveryisomorphisminX isvertical. 3 The dual fibration X ∗ The construction presented in this Section is still elementary, but requires more than just left exactness in the category where it is performed, namely exactness; this implies that good quotients exist for equivalence relations, and that maps on such a quotientcan be defined by assigningvalueson representativeelementsfor the equivalence classes. – We present the construction in the exact category of sets,forsimplicity. Given a fibration p :X →B. We describe another category X ∗ over B, as follows: The objects of X ∗ are the same as those of X ; the arrows X →Y are represented byvh spans,in thefollowingsense: 3 Definition3.1 Avh span inX fromX toY isa diagraminX of theform h · ✲ Y v (2) ❄ X withvvertical andh cartesian. The set of arrows in X ∗ from X to Y are equivalence classes of vh spans from X to Y, for the equivalence relation ≡ given by (v,h) ≡ (v′,h′) if there exists a verticalisomorphismi (necessarily unique)inX so that i.v.=v′ andi.h=h′. (3) We denote the equivalence class of the vh span (v,h) by {(v,h)}. They are the arrows of X ∗; the direction of a the arrow {(v,h)} is determined by its cartesian part h. Composition has to be described in terms of representative pairs; it is in fact the standard composite of spans, but let us be explicit: If z is represented by j (v ,h ) for j =1,2, then z .z is represented by (w,k), where k is cartesian over j j 1 2 p (h )and wis vertical,andthesquaredisplayedcommutes: 1 k h · ✲ · 2 ✲ · w v 2 ❄ ❄ · ✲ · (4) h 1 v 1 ❄ · Such k and w exists (uniquely, up to unique vertical cartesian arrows): construct first k as a cartesian lift of p (h ), then use the universal property of cartesian 1 4 arrowstoconstructw. (Thesquaredisplayedwillthenactuallybeapull-backdia- gram,thusthecompositiondescribedwillbethestandardcompositionofspans.) Compositionofvhspansdoesnotgiveadefinitevhspan,butratheran equiv- alence class of vh spans. So referring to (4), the compositeof {(v ,h )} with the 1 1 of{(v ,h )}is defined by 2 2 {(v ,h )}.{(v ,h )}:={(w.v ,k.h )}. 1 1 2 2 1 2 There is a functor p ∗ from X ∗ to B; on objects, it agrees with p :X →B; and p ∗({(v,h)}) = p (h). Note that if v : X′ → X is vertical, the vh span (v,1) represents amorphismX →X′ inX ∗. Clearly, a vertical arrow in X ∗ has a unique representative span of the form (v,1). So the fibres of p ∗ : X ∗ →B are canonically isomorphic to the duals of thefibres ofp :X →B, i.e. (X∗) ∼=(X )op;soX ∗ is“fibrewisedual”toX A A (butisnotingeneraldualtoX ,sincethefunctorp ∗:X ∗→Bisstillacovariant functor). The arrows in X ∗, we call comorphisms; it is ususally harmless to use thename“comorphism”alsoforarepresenting vhspan (v,h). There are twospecial classes ofcomorphisms: thefirst class consistsofthose comorphismsthat can berepresented by a pair(v,1)where 1 is the relevantiden- tity arrow. They are precisely the vertical arrows for X ∗ → B. – The second classconsistsofthosecomorphismsthatcanberepresentedbyapair(1,h)where 1 is the relevant identity arrow. We shall see that these are precisely the cartesian morphismsinX ∗. ’ Wefirst notethatif(v,h)represents an arbitrary arrow inX ∗,then (v,h)∈{(v,1)}.{(1,h)}; (5) thisiswitnessedbythediagram 1 h · ✲ · ✲ · 1 1 ❄ ❄ · ✲ · 1 v ❄ · 5 sincetheupperleft squareis oftheform consideredin (4). Proposition3.2 An arrow g is cartesian in X ∗ iff it admits a vh representative oftheform(1,h). Proof. Inonedirection,let(1,h)representacomorphismY →Z overb ∈B,and let (v,k) represent a comorphism X →Z over a .b . We display these data as the fullarrows inthefollowingdisplay(in X andB): · vX❄..............k...′...............✲..Yk ✲✲Z; h : : : · ✲ · ✲ · a b The dotted arrow k′ comes about by using the universal property of the cartesian arrow h in X . Since k and h are Cartesian, then so is k′, by the Lemma 1.1. So (v,k′)isacomorphismovera ,and(v,k′).(1.h)≡(v,k),andusingthecancellation property of Cartesian arrows, (v,k′) is easily seen to be the unique comorphism overa .b composingwith (1,h)togive(v,k). In the other direction, let g be a cartesian arrow in X ∗. Let (w,k) be an arbi- trary representative of g. Then by (5), g={(w,1)}.{(1,k)}. Since g is assumed cartesian in X∗, and {(1,k)} is cartesian by what is already proved, it follows from Lemma1.1 that {(w,1)}is cartesian. Since it is also vertical, it followsthat itisanisomorphisminX ∗,hencewisanisomorphisminX . Sincekiscartesian inX , w−1.k is cartesian as well,and (w,k)≡(1,w−1.k), sog has arepresentativeoftheclaimedform. Proposition3.3 Thefunctorp ∗ :X ∗ →B isa fibrationover B 6 Proof. Let b :A →B be an arrow in B, and letY be an object in over B. Since X →B is a fibration,there existsin X a cartesian arrow h overb , and then the vhspan (1,h)represents, by theabove,acartesian arrow inX ∗ overb . SinceX ∗ →B isafibration, wemayask foritsfibrewisedualX ∗∗: Proposition3.4 ThereisacanonicalisomorphismoverBbetweenX andX ∗∗. Proof. We describe an explicit functor y : X → X ∗∗. Let us denote arrows in X ∗ by dotted arrows; they may be presented by vh spans (v,h) in X . We first describe y on vertical and cartesian arrows separately. For a vertical v in X , say v : X′ → X, we have the vh span (v,1) in X , which represents a vertical arrow v:X′99KX inX ∗;thuswehaveavhspan(v,1)inX ∗,whichinturnrepresents a vertical arrow X → X′ in X ∗∗. This arrow, we take as y(v) ∈ X ∗∗. Briefly, y(v) =((v,1),1). – For a cartesian h : X′ →Y (over b , say), we have a vh span (1,h) in X , which represents a horizontal arrow h : X′ 99KY in X ∗ (cartesian overb ); thuswehaveavhspan(1,h)inX ∗,henceanarrow inX ∗∗, fromX′ to Y whichwetakeas y(h)∈X ∗∗;briefly, y(h)=(1,(1,v)). Then, for a general f : X →Y in X , we factor it v.h with v vertical and h cartesian, andputy(f):=y(v).y(h). Weleavetothereadertoverify thatadiffer- ent choice of v and h gives an equivalent vh span in X ∗, thus the same arrow in X ∗∗. Conversely, given an arrow g : X →Y in X ∗∗, represent it by a vh span in X ∗, (v,h), h X′ ...................✲.. Y . . . . . . . . . v. . . . . . . .❄ X Since v is vertical, we may pick a representative of v in the form (v,1) with v : X →X′, and since h is cartesian in X ∗, we may pick a representative of it if the form (1,h), with h:X′ →Y in X . Then the compositev.h:X →Y makes sense inX , and itgoes byyto thegiveng. Example. Consider a group homomorphism p : X → B. It is a fibration iff p is surjective. Assume this. Then the fibre (over the unique object ∗ of B) is the kernel K of p . Every h ∈ X is Cartesian; the vertical arrows are those of K . Then X∗ is canonically isomorphic to X . For, an element (arrow) (v,h) 7 of X ∗ may be presented by either (1,v−1.h), so may be presented in the form (1,x). The map (v,h) 7→ v−1.h gives a canonical isomorphism J : X ∗ → X . This isomorphism preserves p ; note that the p for X ∗ takes (v,h) to p (h). Let us for clarity denote it p ′, so p ′{(v,h)}=p (h). The kernel K ′ for p ′ consists of elementswhichmayberepresentedintheform(v,1)withv∈K ,soK ′may,asa set,beidentifiedwithK byidentifying(v,1)∈K ′⊆X ∗ withv∈K ⊆X . But this identification is an anti-isomorphism, since (v,1) by J goes to v−1.1 = v−1. So K ′ is identified as a group with K op. Thus we have a diagram of group homomorphisms (−)−1 K op ✲ K ∼ = i ⊆ ❄ J ❄ X ∗ ✲ X ∼ = p ′ p ❄ ❄ B ✲ B id wherei(v)={(v,1)}. IncasewhereB=1,andX isthegroupG,thefourmaps ofthetop squareare moreexplicitly‘thefourgroup isomorphisms (−)−1 Gop i ✲ G v7→{(v,1)} = ❄ J ❄ G∗ ✲ G {(v,h)}7→v−1.h where the inverse of J is given by h7→{(1,h)}. If we denote the inverse of J by j, wecan writetheinformationinthisdiagrammoresymmetrically: i j Gop ✲ G∗ ✛ G withi(v):={(v,1)}and j(h):={(1,h)}. 8 4 The case of a (pseudo-) functor Bop →Cat ItiswellknownthatapseudofunctorF :Bop→Cat,givesrisetoafibrationover B. Itisdescribedin,say,[2]B.1.3,orin[1]II.8.3. Thisfibrationisknownasthe GrothendieckconstructionforF. Wedescibeitbrieflyintermsofthefactorization systemalluded toinSection 1. Given a functor (or just a pseudo-functor) F : Bop →Cat. Then we have a category X whose objects are pairs (X,A) with A an object of B and X an object in F(A). Arrows (X,A) → (Y,B) are pairs (v,a ), where a : A → B and v:X →a ∗(Y)inF(A)(andwherea ∗ denotesthefunctorF(a ):F(B)→F(A)). Thefunctorp :X →B takes thisarrowto a . Let usdenotethearrow (1a ∗(Y),a )by a ⊳Y, thus a ⊳Y a ∗(Y) ✲ Y This is a Cartesian arrow over a in X , and every Cartesian arrow is of this form modulo unique vertical isomorphisms. There is then a canonical factorization of general arrows in X , namely, the arrow given by a pair (v,a ), as above, factors as (X,A) (v,1 ) . A ❄ (a ∗(Y),A) ✲ (Y,B) a ⊳Y LetF′beF followedbythedualizationfunctorCat→Cat. Thenamorphismover a inthefibrationcorrespondingtoF′,from(X,A)to(Y,B),isgivensimilarly,but nowwithv:a ∗(Y)→X,whichintermsofthecategoryF(A)ratherthan(F(A))op maybedisplayedinterms ofthevh span a ⊳Y (a ∗(Y),A) ✲ (Y,B) (v,1 ) , A ❄ (X,A) and from this, it is clear that the fibration corresponding to F′ is isomorphic to X ∗ as described inthepreviousSections. 9 One motivation for the present note is to extract the pure category theory behind “fibrewise contravariant functors" (like fibrewise duality for vector bundles), and “star- bundlefunctors”, asin[Kolaretal,1993]41.2. Thisisstillanongoing project. Icannotimaginethattheconstructions inthepresentnotearenotknown,butIdonot presently knowofanyavailable account. References [1] F.Borceux,HandbookofCategoricalAlgebra,vols.1-3,EncyclopediaofMathemat- icsanditsApplications 50-52(CambridgeUniversityPress1994). [2] P.T. Johnstone, Sketches of an Elephant: a Topos Theory Compendium, vols. 1-2, OxfordLogicGuides44and45(OxfordUniversityPress2002). [3] A.Kock,FibrationsasEilenberg-Moore Algebras, arXiv:1312.1608 v1,2013. [4] I. Kolar, P.W. Michor, and J. Slovak, Natural Operations in Differential Geometry, SpringerVerlag1993. UniversityofAarhus,January 2015 mail: kock(at)math.au.dk 10

See more

The list of books you might like